On his book Emancipation After Hegel: Achieving a Contradictory Revolution
Cover Interview of November 27, 2019
The wide angle
From the first time I tried to read Hegel, I remember how
intimidating I found his language and yet how enticing his ideas were to me. As
a result, I felt the need to translate Hegel’s ideas into my own idiom just so
I could make it clear to myself. Even though Emancipation After Hegel is
a book on Hegel, it is also an act of translation, continuing what I began
during my first reading, except this time I’m also translating Hegel for other
people as well as for myself. In the book, I strive for absolute clarity above
all else, so that there could be no confusion about my claims or about Hegel’s.
I often use an example from a film or from my personal life to clarify a
Hegelian concept, and then I follow this with an interpretation of a similar
move that Hegel makes in his philosophical texts. My effort is to make Hegel
readable and to further the case for his philosophy at the same time. This
involves speaking to two widely disparate audiences, but I myself am in both of
those audiences. I’m at once someone trying to get a foothold in Hegel’s
philosophy and someone who has spent decades reading and studying it.
While doing quite a bit of background reading on Hegel (and
digesting the many introductions that have been written, as well as most of the
criticisms), I discovered that the image of Hegel as a progressive philosopher
is almost ubiquitous. From the perspective of this doxa, his philosophy tells
the story of history progressing toward a better future from a humbler past.
This is true among both his followers and his opponents. The clichéd version of
the progressive image reduces his philosophy to the movement from thesis to
antithesis to synthesis. According to this schema, the famous Hegelian
synthesis solves the contradiction between the thesis and the antithesis. It
grounds the opposition in a higher reality that cancels, transcends, and
uplifts it (which is the triple meaning of the famous untranslatable Hegelian
word Aufhebung).
But the problem is that these terms—thesis, antithesis,
synthesis—never appear in any of Hegel’s writings. The cliché has served to
hide the fact that Hegel sees no possible escape from the necessity of
contradiction. There is no Hegelian synthesis at all. But if we take this basic
misunderstanding as our starting point for thinking about his philosophy, we
can actually see what he’s up to by reversing it. This is one of the wagers of
the book. Hegel’s philosophy does trace out various lines of thought until they
reach a point of contradiction, but he does not then seek a way of solving the
contradiction. Instead, when he resolves one contradiction, he turns to another
line of thinking that remains contradictory in order to keep the relationship
to contradiction alive, until he reaches the point where contradiction appears
as intractable. This is the point that he calls absolute knowing. It is the
point, he believes, when we reconcile ourselves to the ultimate intractability
of contradiction.
[T]he Holocaust transformed our whole way of thinking about war and heroism. War is no longer a proving ground for heroism in the same way it used to be. Instead, war now is something that we must avoid at all costs—because genocides often take place under the cover of war. We are no longer all potential soldiers (though we are that too), but we are all potential victims of the traumas war creates. This, at least, is one important development in the way Western populations envision war, even if it does not always predominate in the thinking of our political leaders.Carolyn J. Dean, Interview of February 01, 2011
The dominant premise in evolution and economics is that a person is being loyal to natural law if he or she attends to self’s interest and welfare before being concerned with the needs and demands of family or community. The public does not realize that this statement is not an established scientific principle but an ethical preference. Nonetheless, this belief has created a moral confusion among North Americans and Europeans because the evolution of our species was accompanied by the disposition to worry about kin and the collectives to which one belongs.Jerome Kagan, Interview of September 17, 2009
The wide angle
From the first time I tried to read Hegel, I remember how intimidating I found his language and yet how enticing his ideas were to me. As a result, I felt the need to translate Hegel’s ideas into my own idiom just so I could make it clear to myself. Even though Emancipation After Hegel is a book on Hegel, it is also an act of translation, continuing what I began during my first reading, except this time I’m also translating Hegel for other people as well as for myself. In the book, I strive for absolute clarity above all else, so that there could be no confusion about my claims or about Hegel’s. I often use an example from a film or from my personal life to clarify a Hegelian concept, and then I follow this with an interpretation of a similar move that Hegel makes in his philosophical texts. My effort is to make Hegel readable and to further the case for his philosophy at the same time. This involves speaking to two widely disparate audiences, but I myself am in both of those audiences. I’m at once someone trying to get a foothold in Hegel’s philosophy and someone who has spent decades reading and studying it.
While doing quite a bit of background reading on Hegel (and digesting the many introductions that have been written, as well as most of the criticisms), I discovered that the image of Hegel as a progressive philosopher is almost ubiquitous. From the perspective of this doxa, his philosophy tells the story of history progressing toward a better future from a humbler past. This is true among both his followers and his opponents. The clichéd version of the progressive image reduces his philosophy to the movement from thesis to antithesis to synthesis. According to this schema, the famous Hegelian synthesis solves the contradiction between the thesis and the antithesis. It grounds the opposition in a higher reality that cancels, transcends, and uplifts it (which is the triple meaning of the famous untranslatable Hegelian word Aufhebung).
But the problem is that these terms—thesis, antithesis, synthesis—never appear in any of Hegel’s writings. The cliché has served to hide the fact that Hegel sees no possible escape from the necessity of contradiction. There is no Hegelian synthesis at all. But if we take this basic misunderstanding as our starting point for thinking about his philosophy, we can actually see what he’s up to by reversing it. This is one of the wagers of the book. Hegel’s philosophy does trace out various lines of thought until they reach a point of contradiction, but he does not then seek a way of solving the contradiction. Instead, when he resolves one contradiction, he turns to another line of thinking that remains contradictory in order to keep the relationship to contradiction alive, until he reaches the point where contradiction appears as intractable. This is the point that he calls absolute knowing. It is the point, he believes, when we reconcile ourselves to the ultimate intractability of contradiction.